Jesusi.com Homepage

 

 

 게시판  검색  자료실  사이트맵  예수와나?

[ 뒤로 ] [ ] [ 위로 ] [ 다음 ]

 
Philosophy 

철학 - 지혜의 탐구


[ 보수주의 ] [ 자유주의 ] [ 민족주의 ] [ 파시즘 ] [ 사회주의 ] [ 공산주의 ] [ 무정부주의 ]


Ideology

이데올로기

 

 

Introduction

An ideology is a form of social or political philosophy in which practical elements are as prominent as theoretical ones; it is a system of ideas that aspires both to explain the world and to change it.

This article describes the nature, history, and significance of ideologies in terms of the philosophical, political, and international contexts in which they have arisen. For discussions of particular categories of ideology, see the articles SOCIALISM , COMMUNISM , ANARCHISM , FASCISM , NATIONALISM , LIBERALISM , and CONSERVATISM .

 

ORIGINS AND CHARACTERISTICS OF IDEOLOGY

The word first made its appearance in French as idéologie at the time of the French Revolution, when it was introduced by a philosopher, A.-L.-C. Destutt de Tracy, as a short name for what he called his "science of ideas," which he claimed to have adapted from the epistemology of the philosophers John Locke and Étienne Bonnot de Condillac, for whom all human knowledge was knowledge of ideas. The fact is, however, that he owed rather more to the English philosopher Francis Bacon, whom he revered no less than did the earlier French philosophers of the Enlightenment. It was Bacon who had proclaimed that the destiny of science was not only to enlarge man's knowledge but also to "improve the life of men on earth," and it was this same union of the programmatic with the intellectual that distinguished Destutt de Tracy's idéologie from those theories, systems, or philosophies that were essentially explanatory. The science of ideas was a science with a mission; it aimed at serving men, even saving them, by ridding their minds of prejudice and preparing them for the sovereignty of reason.

Destutt de Tracy and his fellow idéologues devised a system of national education that they believed would transform France into a rational and scientific society. Their teaching combined a fervent belief in individual liberty with an elaborate program of state planning, and for a short time under the Directory (1795-99) it became the official doctrine of the French Republic. Napoleon at first supported Destutt de Tracy and his friends, but he soon turned against them, and in December 1812 he even went so far as to attribute blame for France's military defeats to the influence of the idéologues, of whom he spoke with scorn.

Thus ideology has been from its inception a word with a marked emotive content, though Destutt de Tracy presumably had intended it to be a dry, technical term. Such was his own passionate attachment to the science of ideas, and such was the high moral worth and purpose he assigned to it, that the word idéologie was bound to possess for him a strongly laudatory character. And equally, when Napoleon linked the name of idéologie with what he had come to regard as the most detestable elements in Revolutionary thought, he invested the same word with all of his feelings of disapprobation and mistrust. Ideology was, from this time on, to play this double role of a term both laudatory and abusive not only in French but also in German, English, Italian, and all the other languages of the world into which it was either translated or transliterated.

Some historians of philosophy have called the 19th century the age of ideology, not because the word itself was then so widely used, but because so much of the thought of the time can be distinguished from that prevailing in the previous centuries by features that would now be called ideological. Even so, there is a limit to the extent to which one can speak today of an agreed use of the word. The subject of ideology is a controversial one, and it is arguable that at least some part of this controversy derives from disagreement as to the definition of the word ideology. One can, however, discern both a strict and a loose way of using it. In the loose sense of the word, ideology may mean any kind of action-oriented theory or any attempt to approach politics in the light of a system of ideas. Ideology in the stricter sense stays fairly close to Destutt de Tracy's original conception and may be identified by five characteristics: (1) it contains an explanatory theory of a more or less comprehensive kind about human experience and the external world; (2) it sets out a program, in generalized and abstract terms, of social and political organization; (3) it conceives the realization of this program as entailing a struggle; (4) it seeks not merely to persuade but to recruit loyal adherents, demanding what is sometimes called commitment; (5) it addresses a wide public but may tend to confer some special role of leadership on intellectuals. In this article the noun ideology is used only in its strict sense; the adjective ideological is used to refer to ideology as broadly defined.

On the basis of the five features above, then, one can recognize as ideologies systems as diverse as Destutt de Tracy's own science of ideas, the Positivism of the French philosopher Auguste Comte, Communism and several other types of Socialism, Fascism, Nazism, and certain kinds of nationalism. That all these "-isms" belong to the 19th or 20th century may suggest that ideologies are no older than the word itself--that they belong essentially to a period in which secular belief has increasingly replaced traditional religious faith.

 

THE PHILOSOPHICAL CONTEXT

 

Ideology and religion.

Ideologies, in fact, are sometimes spoken of as if they belonged to the same logical category as religions. Both are assuredly in a certain sense "total" systems, concerned at the same time with questions of truth and questions of conduct; but the differences between ideologies and religions are perhaps more important than the similarities. A religious theory of reality is constructed in terms of a divine order and is seldom, like that of the ideologist, centred on this world alone. A religion may present a vision of a just society, but it cannot easily have a practical political program. The emphasis of religion is on faith and worship; its appeal is to inwardness and its aim the redemption or purification of the human spirit. An ideology speaks to the group, the nation, or the class. Some religions acknowledge their debt to revelation, whereas ideology always believes, however mistakenly, that it lives by reason alone. Both, it may be said, demand commitment, but it may be doubted whether commitment has ever been a marked feature of those religions into which a believer is inducted in infancy.

Even so, it is in certain religious movements that the first ideological elements in the modern world can be seen. The city of Florence, which in so many fields witnessed the birth of modernity, produced perhaps the first "ideological" Christian. The attempt of Girolamo Savonarola to construct a puritan utopia was marked by several of the qualities by which one recognizes a modern ideology: Savonarola treated the vision of a Christian community as a model that men should actually seek to realize in the here and now. His method was to dominate the state through an appeal to the populace, and then to use the powers of the state to control both the economy and the private lives of the citizens. The enterprise was given a militant spirit; it was presented by Savonarola as being at one and the same time an outward struggle against papal corruption, the commercial ethos, and Renaissance Humanism, and an inward struggle against worldly ambitions and carnal desires.

Savonarola had numerous followers in his attempt to give Christianity an ideological dimension: he inspired Calvin's Geneva and the Puritan communities of the New World. Indeed, in both the Reformation and the Counter-Reformation, when Christianity was invested with a new militancy and a new intolerance, when a new emphasis was placed on creeds and conversion, religion itself moved that much nearer to ideology.

 

Ideology in early political philosophy.

The Italian political philosopher Niccolò Machiavelli was one of Savonarola's sharpest critics, but he was also, like him, a precursor of modern ideologists. Historians who speak of him only as an immoralist overlook the extent to which Machiavelli was a man with an ideal--a republican ideal. Rousseau recognized this when he spoke of The Prince as a "handbook for republicans." Machiavelli's dream was to see revived in modern Italy a republic as glorious as that of ancient Rome, and he suggested that it could be achieved only by means of a revolution that had the strength of will to liquidate its enemies. Machiavelli was the first to link ideology with terror, but he was too much of a political scientist to enact the role of the ideologue.

Seventeenth-century England occupies an important place in the history of ideology. Although there were then no fully fledged ideologies in the strict sense of the term, political theory, like politics itself, began to acquire certain ideological characteristics. The swift movement of revolutionary forces throughout the 17th century created a demand for theories to explain and justify the radical action that was often taken. Locke's Two Treatises of Government is an outstanding example of literature written to justify the rights of man against absolutism. This growth of abstract theory in the 17th century, this increasing tendency to construct systems and discuss politics in terms of principles, marks the emergence of the ideological style. In political conversation generally it was accompanied by a growing use of concepts such as right and liberty--ideals in terms of which actual policies were judged.

 

Hegel and Marx.

Although the word ideology in the sense derived from Destutt de Tracy's understanding has passed into modern usage, it is important to notice the particular sense that ideology is given in Hegelian and Marxist philosophy, where it is used in a pejorative way. Ideology there becomes a word for what these philosophers also call "false consciousness." G.W.F. Hegel argued that people were instruments of history; they enacted roles that were assigned to them by forces they did not understand; the meaning of history was hidden from them. Only the philosopher could expect to understand things as they were. This Hegelian enterprise of interpreting reality and reconciling the world to itself was condemned by certain critics as an attempt to provide an ideology of the status quo, in that if individuals were indeed mere ciphers whose actions were determined by external forces, then there was little point in trying to change or improve political and other circumstances. This is a criticism Karl Marx took up, and it is the argument he developed in The German Ideology and other earlier writings. Ideology in this sense is a set of beliefs with which people deceive themselves; it is theory that expresses what they are led to think, as opposed to that which is true; it is false consciousness.

Marx, however, was not consistent in his use of the word ideology, for he did not always use the term pejoratively, and some of his references to it clearly imply the possibility of an ideology being true. Twentieth-century Marxists, who have frequently discarded the pejorative sense of ideology altogether, have been content to speak of Marxism as being itself an ideology. In certain Communist countries "ideological institutes" have been established, and party philosophers are commonly spoken of as party ideologists. Marxism is an excellent example, a paradigm, of an ideology.

 

The sociology of knowledge.

The use of the word ideology in the pejorative sense of false consciousness is found not only in the writings of Marx himself but in those of other exponents of what has come to be known as the sociology of knowledge, including the German sociologists Max Weber and Karl Mannheim, and numerous lesser figures. Few such writers are wholly consistent in their use of the term, but what is characteristic of their approach is their method of regarding idea systems as the outcome or expression of certain interests. In calling such idea systems ideologies, they are treating them as things whose true nature is concealed; they consider the task of sociological research to be the unveiling of what Mannheim called the "life conditions which produce ideologies."

From this perspective, the economic science of Adam Smith, for example, is not to be understood as an independent intellectual construction or to be judged in terms of its truth, consistency, or clarity; rather, it is to be seen as the expression of bourgeois interests, as part of the ideology of capitalism.

The sociology of knowledge in its more recent formulations has sought support in Freudian psychology (notably in borrowing from Freud the concepts of the unconscious and of rationalization), in order to suggest that ideologies are the unconscious rationalizations of class interests. This refinement has enabled sociologists of knowledge to rid their theory of the disagreeable and unscientific element of bald accusation; they no longer have to brand Adam Smith as a deliberate champion of the bourgeois ethos but can see him now as simply the unconscious spokesman of capitalism. At the same time, these sociologists of knowledge have argued that Freudian psychology is itself no less a form of ideology than is Adam Smith's economics, for Freud's method of psychoanalysis is essentially a technique for adjusting rebellious minds to the demands and constraints of bourgeois society.

Critics of the sociology of knowledge have argued that if all philosophy is ideology, then the sociology of knowledge must itself be an ideology like any other idea system and equally devoid of independent validity; that if all seeming truth is veiled rationalization of interest, then the sociology of knowledge cannot be true. It has been suggested that although Weber and Mannheim inspired most of the work that has been done by sociologists of knowledge their own writings may perhaps be exempted from this criticism, if only on the ground that neither of them put forward a consistent or unambiguous theory of ideology. Both used the word ideology in different ways at different times. Weber was in part concerned to reverse Marx's theory that all idea systems are products of economic structures, by demonstrating conversely that some economic structures are the product of idea systems (that Protestantism, for example, generated capitalism and not capitalism Protestantism). Mannheim, on the other hand, tried to restore in a more elaborate form Marx's suggestion that ideologies are the product of the social structure. But Mannheim's analysis may have been obscured by his proposal that the word ideology should be reserved for idea systems that are more or less conservative, and the word utopia for idea systems of a more revolutionary or millenarian nature. Mannheim did not, however, remain faithful to this stipulative definition, even in his book entitled Ideology and Utopia.

On the other hand, Mannheim was well aware of the implication of the doctrine that all idea systems have a class basis and a class bias. As a way out of the dilemma he envisaged the possibility of a classless class of intellectuals, a "socially unattached intelligentsia," as he put it, capable of thinking independently by virtue of its independence from any class interest or affiliation. Such a detached group might hope to acquire knowledge that was not ideology. This vision of a small elite of superior minds rising above the myths of ordinary society seemed to some readers to put Mannheim closer to Plato than to Marx and to cast new doubts on the claim of the sociology of knowledge to be a science.

 

THE POLITICAL CONTEXT

 

Ideology, rationalism, and romanticism.

If some theorists emphasize the kinship between ideology and various forms of religious enthusiasm, others stress the connection between ideology and what they call rationalism, or the attempt to understand politics in terms of abstract ideas rather than of lived experience. Like Napoleon, who held that ideology is par excellence the work of intellectuals, some theorists are suspicious of those who think they know about politics because they have read many books; they believe that politics can be learned only by an apprenticeship to politics itself.

Such people are not unsympathetic to political theories, such as Locke's, but they argue that their value resides in the facts that are derived from experience. Michael Oakeshott in England has described Locke's theory of political liberty as an "abridgment" of the Englishman's traditional understanding of liberty, and has suggested that once such a conception is uprooted from the tradition that has given it meaning it becomes a rationalistic doctrine or metaphysical abstraction, like those liberties contained in the Declaration of the Rights of Man, which were so much talked about after the French Revolution but rarely actually enjoyed, in France or elsewhere.

Whereas Oakeshott has seen ideology as a form of rationalism, Edward Shils, a U.S. political scientist, has seen it more as a product of, among other things, romanticism with an extremist character. His argument is that romanticism has fed into and swelled the seas of ideological politics by its cult of the ideal and by its scorn for the actual, especially its scorn for what is mediated by calculation and compromise. Since civil politics demands both compromise and contrivance and calls for a prudent self-restraint and responsible caution, he suggests that civil politics is bound to be repugnant to romanticism. Hence Shils concludes that the romantic spirit is naturally driven toward ideological politics.

 

Ideology and terror.

The "total" character of ideology, its extremism and violence, have been analyzed by other critics, among whom the French philosopher-writer Albert Camus and the Austrian-born British philosopher Sir Karl Popper merit particular attention. Beginning as an Existentialist who subscribed to the view that "the universe is absurd," Camus passed to a personal affirmation of justice and human decency as compelling values to be realized in conduct. An Algerian by birth, Camus also appealed to what he believed to be the "Mediterranean" tradition of moderation and human warmth and joy in living as opposed to the "northern" Germanic tradition of fanatical, puritan devotion to metaphysical abstractions. In his book The Rebel (L'Homme révolté), he argued that the true rebel is not the man who conforms to the orthodoxy of some revolutionary ideology, but a man who could say "no" to injustice. He suggested that the true rebel would prefer the politics of reform, such as that of modern trade-union socialism, to the totalitarian politics of Marxism or similar movements. The systematic violence of ideology--the crimes de logique that were committed in its name--appeared to Camus to be wholly unjustifiable. Hating cruelty, he believed that the rise of ideology in the modern world had added enormously to human suffering. Though he was willing to admit that the ultimate aim of most ideologies was to diminish human suffering, he argued that good ends did not authorize the use of evil means.

A somewhat similar plea for what he called "piecemeal social engineering" was put forward by Popper, who argued that ideology rests on a logical mistake: namely the notion that history can be transformed into science. In The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Logik der Forschung), Popper suggested that the true method of science was not one of observation, hypothesis, and confirmation but one of conjecture and experiment, in which the concept of falsification played a crucial role. By this concept he meant that in science there is a continuing process of trial and error; conjectures are put to the test of experiment, and those that are not falsified are provisionally accepted; thus there is no definitive knowledge but only provisional knowledge that is constantly being corrected. Popper saw in the enterprise of ideology an attempt to find certainty in history and to produce predictions on the model of what were supposed to be scientific predictions. Ideologists, he argued, because they have a false notion of what science is, can produce only prophecies, which are quite distinct from scientific predictions and which have no scientific validity whatever. Though Popper was well disposed toward the idea of a "scientific" approach to politics and ethics, he suggested that a full awareness of the importance of trial and error in science would prompt one to look for similar forms of "negative judgment" elsewhere.

By no means are all ideologists explicit champions of violence, but it is characteristic of ideology both to exalt action and to regard action in terms of a military analogy. Some observers have pointed out that one has only to consider the prose style of the founders of most ideologies to be struck by the military and warlike language that they habitually use, including words like struggle, resist, march, victory, and overcome; the literature of ideology is replete with martial expressions. In such a view, commitment to an ideology becomes a form of enlistment so that to become the adherent of an ideology is to become a combatant or partisan.

In the years that followed World War II, a number of ideological writers went beyond the mere use of military language and made frank avowals of their desire for violence--not that it was a new thing to praise violence. The French political philosopher Georges Sorel, for example, had done so before World War I in his book Reflections on Violence. Sorel was usually regarded as being more a Fascist than a Socialist. He also used the word violence in his own special way; by violence Sorel meant passion, not the throwing of bombs and the burning of buildings.

Violence found eloquent champions in several black militant writers of the 1960s, notably the Martinican theorist Frantz Fanon. Moreover, several of the French philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre's dramatic writings turn on the theme that "dirty hands" are necessary in politics and that a man with so-called bourgeois inhibitions about bloodshed cannot usefully serve a revolutionary cause. Sartre's attachment to the ideal of revolution tended to increase as he grew older, and in some of his later writings he suggested that violence might even be a good thing in itself.

In considering Sartre's views on the subject of ideology it must be noted that Sartre sometimes used the word ideology in a sense peculiarly his own. In an early section of his Search for a Method (Critique de la raison dialectique), Sartre drew a distinction between philosophies and ideologies in which he reserved the term philosophy for those major systems of thought, such as the Rationalism of Descartes or the Idealism of Hegel, which dominate men's minds at a certain moment in history. He defined an ideology as a minor system of ideas, living on the margin of the genuine philosophy and exploiting the domain of the greater system. What Sartre proposed in this work was a revitalization and modernization of the "major philosophy" of Marxism through the integration of elements drawn from the "ideology," or minor system, of Existentialism. What emerged from the book was a theory in which the Existentialist elements are more conspicuous than the Marxist.

 

Ideology and pragmatism.

A distinction is often drawn between the ideological and the pragmatic approach to politics, the latter being understood as the approach that treats particular issues and problems purely on their merits and does not attempt to apply doctrinal, preconceived remedies. Theorists have debated whether or not politics has become less ideological and whether a pragmatic approach can be shown to be better than an ideological one.

On the first question, there seemed to be good reason for thinking that after the death of Stalin and the repudiation of Stalinism by the Communist Party, the Soviet Union, at least, was becoming more interested in the "pragmatic" concerns of national security and the balance of power and less interested in the ideological aim of fostering universal Communism. This in turn seemed to many to have resulted--in both the United States and the Soviet Union--in a shift toward a pragmatic policy of coexistence and a peaceful division of spheres of influence. There were indications in many countries that the old antagonisms between capitalist and socialist ideologies were giving way to a search for techniques for making a mixed economy work more effectively for the good of all.

But while many observers believed that there was much evidence of a decline of ideology in the latter 1950s, others believed that there were equally manifest signs in the following decade of a revival of ideology, if not within the major political parties, then at least among the public generally. Throughout the world various left-wing movements emerged to challenge the whole ethos on which pragmatic politics was based. Not all these ideologies were coherent, and none possessed the elaborate intellectual structure of the 19th-century ideologies; but together they served to demonstrate that the end of ideology was not yet at hand.

As suggested earlier, certain controversies about ideology have to some extent been rooted in the ambiguity of the word itself, and this is perhaps especially relevant to the confrontation between ideology and pragmatism, since the word pragmatism raises problems no less intractable than those involved in connection with the word ideology. In the senses outlined at the beginning of this article, ideology is manifestly not the only alternative to pragmatism in politics, and to reject ideology would not necessarily be to adopt pragmatism. Ordinary language does not yet yield as many words as political science needs to clarify the question, and it becomes necessary to introduce such expressions as belief system, or to name the relevant distinctions, to further the analysis.

Almost any approach to politics constitutes a belief system of one kind or another. Some such belief systems are more structured, more ordered, and generally systematic than others. Though an ideology is a type of belief system, not all belief systems are ideologies. One man's belief system may consist of a congeries of ill-assorted prejudices and inarticulate assumptions. Another's may be the result of deep reflection and careful study. It is sometimes felt to be convenient to speak of a belief system of this latter type as a philosophy or, better, to distinguish it from philosophy in the technical or academic sense, as a Weltanschauung (literally, a "view of the world").

The confrontation between ideology and pragmatism may be more instructive if it is translated into a distinction between the ideological and the pragmatic, taking these two adjectives as extremes on a sliding scale. From this perspective, it becomes possible to speak of differences of degree, to speak of an approach to politics as being more or less ideological, more or less pragmatic. At the same time it becomes possible to speak of a belief system such as liberalism as lending itself to a variety of forms, tending at the one extreme toward the ideological, and at the other toward the pragmatic.

 

THE CONTEXT OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS

It has been said that ideology has transformed international relationships in the 20th century--in appearance at least. Earlier centuries experienced dynastic wars, national, civil, and imperial wars, and diplomacy designed to further national security or national expansion or to promote mutual advantages and general peace. Such factors, indeed, appeared to govern international relations until recent times. International relations today are seemingly dominated more often than not by the exigencies of "-isms": wars are fought, alliances are made, and treaties are signed because of ideological considerations. The balance of power in the contemporary world is a balance weighted by ideological commitment. "The Communist bloc" confronts "the Free peoples," and in the "Third World" emergent nations cultivate a nationalist, anticolonialist ideology in their search for identity and their efforts to achieve modernity.

But this is not to assert that ideological wars, or ideological diplomacy, are entirely new. What has become the most conspicuous element in contemporary international relations--so conspicuous that other elements are often entirely ignored--was present, to a lesser degree, in earlier international relations. It is necessary here to distinguish between the actual events of history and the interpretations that are put on history, for some events lend themselves more readily than others to an ideological interpretation. The ideological perspective has become increasingly significant as the general public has come to play a role in considering questions of war and peace. When questions of defense and diplomacy were settled by kings and their ministers and wars were fought by professional soldiers and sailors, the public was not expected to have any opinion about international relations, and in such a situation there was little place for ideology.

 

Ideology in the World Wars.

In the course of World War I, however, a new element appeared to have been introduced. The war was seen by those who experienced it as being in its early stages a national war of the traditional kind, and as such it was not at first expected to assume any profoundly disturbing form. Each combatant people viewed itself as fighting for king and country in a just war. But by 1916 the Allies were being urged to think of their endeavour as a war "to make the world safe for democracy," and the Germans, on their side, were correspondingly encouraged to visualize the war as a struggle of "culture" against "barbarism." On both sides, the casualties were far more terrible than anyone had foreseen, and the need to sustain the will to war by an appeal to ideology was plainly felt by all the nations involved. Whether such "war aims" were really the main objectives of the governments concerned is another question; what is important is that, as the need was increasingly felt for a justification of war, the justification took an ideological form. Whether or not World War I changed its real nature between 1914 and 1918, the prevailing conception of it underwent significant alteration. This became more marked after the Russian Revolution of 1917, when the Bolsheviks submitted to harsh German peace terms for reasons thatwere not only practical but ideological--namely, the preservation and promotion of Communism. Pres. Woodrow Wilson took the United States into the war on the Allied side with an alternative ideological vision--that of ensuring permanent peace through the League of Nations and of establishing democratic governments in all the conquered countries.

The rise of Communism clearly marked a corresponding increase in the role of ideology in international relations. Fascism helped to speed the process. The Spanish Civil War of the 1930s was an almost clear-cut confrontation between the ideologies of left and right (not entirely clear-cut because of the ambiguous relationship between Communism and anarchism).

The precise extent of ideological commitment in World War II is a matter of some controversy. At one level, the 1939 war is seen as a continuation of the war of 1914. Two of the leading protagonists--Great Britain and the United States--agreed more in their anti-ideological stance and their hostility to Nazism than in promoting an alternative ideology. Pres. Franklin D. Roosevelt, suspicious of British and French imperialism and eager to cultivate a progressive ideological outlook, was critical of Prime Minister Winston Churchill's politics, hostile toward Charles de Gaulle's, but surprisingly tolerant of Joseph Stalin's. The revival of Wilson's idealistic war aims in the Atlantic Charter provided a basis for a kind of general ideological union of the Allies. But such formulations proved to be of small significance compared to the profound ideological commitment of the Soviet Union to Communism, and that of the United States to an international position more ideologically anti-Communist than pro anything.

 

Ideology of the Cold War.

What came to be called the Cold War in the 1950s must be understood, to a large extent, as an ideological confrontation, and, whereas Communism is manifestly an ideology, the "non-Communism," or even the "anti-Communism," of the West is negatively ideological. To oppose one ideology is not necessarily to subscribe to another, although there is a strong body of opinion in the West that feels that the free world needs a coherent ideology if it is to resist successfully an opposing ideology.

The connection between international wars and ideology can be better expressed in terms of a difference of degree rather than of kind: some wars are more ideological than others, although there is no clear boundary between an ideological and nonideological war. An analogy with the religious wars of the past is evident, and there is indeed some historical continuity between the two types of war. The Christian Crusades against the Turks and the wars between Catholics and Protestants in early modern Europe have much in common with the ideological conflicts of the contemporary period. Religious wars are often communal wars, as witness those between Hindus and Muslims in India; but an "ideological" element of a kind can be discovered in many religious wars, even those narrated in the Old Testament, in which the people of Israel are described as fighting for the cause of righteousness--fighting, in other words, for a universal abstraction as distinct from a local and practical aim. In the past this "ideological" element has in the main been subsidiary; what is characteristic of the modern period is that the ideological element has become increasingly dominant, first in the religious wars (and the related diplomacy) that followed the Reformation and then in the political wars and diplomacy of recent times. (M.C.)

 

 

이데올로기 (idéologie). 이론과 실천의 양 측면에서 중요한 의미를 갖는 사회·정치 철학의 한 형태. 세계를 설명하고 변화시키는 것을 뒷받침하는 관념체계이다.

이데올로기의 기원과 특징

이데올로기(idéologie)라는 말은 프랑스 혁명기에 철학자 A. L. C. 데스튀트 드 트라시가 자신의 '관념의 과학'의 약칭으로 도입하면서 처음 등장했다. 그는 관념의 과학이 모든 인간지식을 관념에 관한 지식으로 본 철학자 존 로크와 에티엔 보노 드 콩디야크의 인식론을 각색한 것이라고 설명했으나, 사실은 영국의 철학자 프랜시스 베이컨에게 더 많은 빚을 지고 있다. 베이컨은 과학의 운명은 인간 지식의 확대뿐만 아니라 '지구 위의 인간의 삶을 개선하는 일'이라고 선언했다. 베이컨처럼 지식과 실용을 결합하는 것이야말로 설명을 본질로 하는 이론·철학과 데스튀트 드 트라시의 이데올로기를 구별짓는 특징이다. 관념의 과학은 인간정신에서 편견을 몰아내고 이성을 복권함으로써 인간에 봉사하고 구원하는 것을 목표로 삼았다. 프랑스를 합리적·과학적 사회로 변혁하리라 믿고 국민교육체계를 고안한 데스튀트 드 트라시와 동료 이데올로그(idéologue)들의 가르침은 1795~99년 프랑스 총재정부의 공인학설이 되었다. 그런데 처음에는 그들을 지지했던 나폴레옹이 곧 등을 돌렸고 1812년 12월 프랑스군의 패배를 이데올로그들의 탓으로 돌리기까지 했다. 이리하여 이데올로기는 시작부터 뚜렷한 감정적 함축을 지닌 용어가 되어 버렸다. 이데올로기는 데스튀트 드 트라시가 관념의 과학에 정열적으로 애정을 쏟고 숭고한 도덕적 가치를 부여함으로써 좋은 의미를 가졌다가 그후 나폴레옹이 혁명사상의 혐오스런 요소들을 이 낱말과 결합함으로써 온갖 비난과 불신의 느낌으로 채워졌다. 이때부터 이데올로기는 프랑스어뿐만 아니라 전세계 언어로 번역될 때 칭찬과 욕설의 이중성을 띠게 되었다.

이데올로기라는 말은 협의와 광의로 구별할 수 있는데 이데올로기를 둘러싼 논쟁이 적어도 어떤 부분은 용어의 정의가 일치하지 않는 데서 비롯되기 때문이다. 광의의 이데올로기는 체계적인 관념의 인도를 받는 모든 종류의 행동지향적 이론이나 관념 체계에 비추어 정치에 접근하는 모든 시도를 뜻한다. 협의의 이데올로기는 다음의 5가지 특징으로 나타낼 수 있으며, 데스튀트 드 트라시의 원래 견해에 매우 가깝다. ① 이데올로기는 인간경험과 외부세계에 관한 포괄적인 설명이론을 포함한다. ② 이데올로기는 일반적·추상적 용어로 사회·정치를 조직하는 프로그램을 제시한다. ③ 이데올로기는 이 프로그램의 실현에는 투쟁이 뒤따를 것이라고 본다. ④ 이데올로기는 때때로 서약을 요구하면서 충실한 지지자를 모으려 한다. ⑤ 이데올로기는 광범한 대중을 향하며 지식인에게 특별한 지도역할을 부여하는 경향을 띤다.

철학적 맥락

이데올로기와 종교

이데올로기는 종종 종교와 동일한 범주에 속한다고 이야기된다. 2가지 모두 총체적 체계이며 진리 및 행위 문제와 관련이 있다. 그러나 그보다 중요한 것은 이데올로기와 종교의 차이이다. 종교이론은 신적 질서에 따라 세워지며 이데올로기처럼 현실세계에만 관심을 집중하지 않는다. 종교는 정의로운 사회의 이상향을 제시할 수 있지만 정치적 실천 프로그램을 가지기 어려우며, 믿음·예배를 강조하고 영성(靈性)에 호소하며 인간정신의 구원·정화를 목적으로 한다. 이데올로기는 집단·민족·계급을 향해 말하며, 계시에 의지하는 종교에 반해 판단을 그르치는 일이 있더라도 이성에만 의지한다고 믿는다. 근대 세계 최초의 이데올로기적 요소는 몇몇 종교운동에서 찾아볼 수 있다. 지롤라모 사보나롤라는 최초의 '이데올로기적'인 그리스도교도였으며, 프로테스탄트적 유토피아를 건설하려 했다. 그는 그리스도교 공동체의 이상향을 지금 우리가 실현해야 할 모델로 여겼고, 실현방법으로서 하층민에 호소해 국가를 지배하고 경제와 시민의 사생활을 감독하기 위해 국가권력을 이용하자고 주장했다. 그는 그리스도교에 이데올로기적 차원을 부여한 시도 때문에 수많은 추종자를 얻었으며, 칼뱅의 제네바 및 신대륙의 청교도 공동체에 영감을 주었다.

초기 정치철학에서 이데올로기

이탈리아의 정치철학자 니콜로 마키아벨리는 사보나롤라와 함께 근대 이데올로그의 선구자였다. 마키아벨리의 꿈은 근대 이탈리아에서 고대 로마와 같은 찬란한 공화제가 부활하는 것을 보는 것이었는데, 이는 혁명을 통해서만 달성될 수 있다고 주장했다. 또 마키아벨리는 최초로 이데올로기를 테러와 결합했으나 이데올로그 역할을 하기에는 지나치게 정치학자의 성격이 강했다. 17세기 영국은 이데올로기 역사에서 중요한 위치를 차지한다. 당시 영국에서 혁명세력의 신속한 움직임은 급진적 행동을 설명하고 정당화할 수 있는 이론을 요구했으며, 따라서 정치이론은 정치 자체와 마찬가지로 이데올로기의 성격을 띠게 되었다. 존 로크의 〈통치론 2편 Two Treatises of Government〉(1690)은 절대주의에 대항하는 인간권리를 정당화하기 위해 쓴 대표적 문헌이다. 17세기에 추상적 이론이 성장하고 이론체계의 확립과 정치를 원리에 따라 논의하는 경향이 증가한 것은 이데올로기적 양식의 출현을 두드러지게 보여준다.

헤겔과 마르크스

이데올로기가 헤겔과 마르크스의 철학에서 부여받은 특수한 의미를 주목하는 것은 중요한 일이다. 여기서 이데올로기란 '허위의식'을 나타내는 비난조의 의미를 지닌다. 헤겔에 따르면 인민은 역사의 도구로서 자신도 알지 못하는 외적인 힘이 자신에게 부여한 역할을 수행하며, 그리하여 역사의 의미는 인민의 배후에 숨어 있다. 현실을 이렇게 해석해서 현실과 타협하려는 헤겔의 시도는 현상유지 이데올로기를 제공하는 것이다. 왜냐하면 만일 개인이 외적 힘에 의해 자신의 행동을 결정하는 보잘것없는 존재라면 상황을 바꾸거나 개선하려는 노력은 거의 의미가 없기 때문이다. 바로 이것이 헤겔에 대한 카를 마르크스의 비판이며, 〈독일 이데올로기 Die Deutsche Ideologie〉와 그밖의 초기저작에서 전개한 주장이다. 이런 의미의 이데올로기는 자기 자신을 속이는 일련의 믿음을 뜻한다. 마르크스에 따르면 진리와 반대되는 것을 생각하도록 이끄는 이론이 이데올로기이자 허위의식이다. 그러나 마르크스는 이 용어를 일관되게 비난조로만 사용한 것이 아니라 참된 이데올로기의 가능성을 내포하는 것으로도 사용했다. 종종 이데올로기의 경멸적 의미를 무시했던 20세기 마르크스주의자는 마르크스주의 자체가 이데올로기로 일컬어지는 데 만족했다. 몇몇 공산주의 나라에서 당 철학자는 보통 당 이데올로그라 불린다. 마르크스주의는 이데올로기의 훌륭한 전형이다.

지식사회학

독일의 사회학자 막스 베버와 카를 만하임을 필두로 하는 지식사회학자의 저작 속에서도 이데올로기는 허위의식이라는 비난적 의미로 사용된다. 이들의 접근방법의 특징은 이데올로기를 특정 이해관계의 결과나 표현으로 여기고 이런 이데올로기를 진짜 성격을 감춘 어떤 것으로 다룬다는 점이다. 그래서 지식사회학자들은 만하임이 말한 '이데올로기를 산출하는 생활조건'의 베일을 벗기는 일을 사회학의 임무라고 생각한다. 이런 관점에서 보면 예컨대 애덤 스미스의 경제학은 독립된 지식 구성물로 인정할 수 없으며 그 자체의 진리 및 일관성에 따라 평가할 수 없고, 오히려 자본주의 이데올로기로써 부르주아의 이해관계를 표현한 것으로 보아야 한다.

최근의 지식사회학은 이데올로기가 계급이익의 무의식적 합리화임을 주장하기 위해 프로이트 심리학을 지지해왔다. 이때문에 지식사회학자들은 지식사회학 이론에서 비과학적이라고 노골적으로 비난받는 요소를 제거할 수 있었다. 왜냐하면 프로이트 심리학을 도입하면 지식사회학자들은 애덤 스미스를 부르주아 특질을 가진 고의적 투사로 더이상 낙인찍지 않고 그저 자본주의의 무의식적 대변인으로 볼 수 있기 때문이다. 이와 동시에 지식사회학자들은 프로이트 심리학이 애덤 스미스의 경제학 못지 않게 이데올로기의 한 형태임을 주장해왔다. 본질적으로 프로이트의 정신분석방법은 반항적 성격의 소유자를 부르주아 사회의 요구와 속박에 적응시키는 기술이기 때문이다. 지식사회학에 대한 비판자들은 모든 철학이 이데올로기라면 지식사회학도 이데올로기임에 틀림없다고 주장한다. 한편 비록 베버와 만하임이 지식사회학자들의 견해에 강한 암시를 주기는 했지만, 두 사람 중 누구도 일관된 이데올로기론을 내놓지 않았기 때문에 그들은 위의 비판에서 벗어날 수도 있다. 베버와 만하임은 이데올로기라는 낱말을 서로 다르게 사용했다. 베버는 경제구조가 이념체계의 산물이라는 점(예를 들면 프로테스탄트주의가 자본주의를 낳았지 그 반대가 아니라는 것)을 논증함으로써 이념체계가 경제구조의 산물이라는 마르크스의 이론을 뒤집는 데 관심을 가졌다. 반면 만하임은 이데올로기가 사회구조의 산물이라는 마르크스의 제안을 좀더 정교한 형태로 되살리려고 노력했다. 그러나 이데올로기라는 낱말은 다소 보수적인 관념체계에서, 유토피아라는 낱말은 좀더 혁명적인 또는 천년왕국적 성격을 가진 관념체계에서 사용해야 한다는 제안 때문에 만하임의 이러한 노력은 빛을 잃은 것 같다. 그는 〈이데올로기와 유토피아 Ideologie und Utopie〉에서조차 이러한 약정적 정의에 충실하지 못했다. 한편 모든 관념체계가 계급 기반과 계급 편견을 가진다는 원리가 함축하고 있는 딜레마에서 빠져나오는 길로서 만하임이 설정한 계급 아닌 계급인 지식인, 즉 '사회적 중립을 지키는 인텔리겐치아'의 가능성은 계급 이해나 제휴에서 벗어날 수 있다면 생각해볼 만한 문제이다. 그러나 뛰어난 정신을 지닌 소수 엘리트를 이상으로 제시한 것은 만하임이 마르크스보다 플라톤에 더 가깝다는 인상을 주고 지식사회학이 과학이라는 주장에 새로운 의문을 던진 것으로 보인다.

정치적 맥락

이데올로기·합리주의·낭만주의

어떤 이론가들은 이데올로기와 종교적 열광 사이의 유사성을 강조하는 반면 다른 이론가들은 이데올로기와 합리주의의 연관, 산 경험보다 추상적 이념에 따라 정치를 이해하려는 시도와 이데올로기의 연관을 강조한다. 또 책을 통해 정치에 관해 안다고 생각하는 사람을 믿지 못하고 도제살이함으로써만 정치를 배울 수 있다고 믿는 이론가도 있다. 왜냐하면 정치이론의 가치는 경험에서 나온다고 여기기 때문이다. 이데올로기를 합리주의의 한 형태로 본 영국의 마이클 오크쇼트는 로크의 정치적 자유 이론을 영국인의 자유에 대한 전통적인 이해의 하나의 '요약'이라 보고, 이같은 개념을 그 전통과 연관짓지 않으면 프랑스 인권선언 속의 여러 자유개념처럼 합리주의적 원리나 형이상학적 추상이 된다고 했다. 반면에 이데올로기를 극단적 낭만주의의 산물로 본 미국의 정치학자 에드워드 실스는 낭만주의가 이상을 예찬하고 현실적인 것, 특히 타산과 타협을 경멸함으로써 이데올로기적 정치라는 파도에 휩쓸리게 된다고 보았다. 시민정치는 타협·책략·자제·신중함을 요구하므로 낭만주의와는 다르며, 따라서 낭만주의 정신은 자연스럽게 이데올로기적 정치로 질주한다고 결론지었다.

국제관계의 맥락

세계전쟁에서의 이데올로기

이데올로기는 20세기 국제관계를 뒤바꾸어놓은 것으로 평가된다. 이데올로기적 고려 때문에 전쟁이 일어나고 동맹을 맺고 조약을 체결하는 일이 많았다. 공산주의 진영은 자유주의 진영과 대결하고, 제3세계의 신생국가들은 민족주의·반식민주의 이데올로기를 배양하여 정체성을 확립하고 근대화를 이룩하려 했다. 그러나 이데올로기 전쟁, 이데올로기 외교가 완전히 새로운 현상은 아니다. 초기의 국제관계에서는 약했던 이데올로기적 요소가 현대에 와서 가장 두드러진 요소가 되었다는 점만 새로울 뿐이다. 특히 세계대전에서 이데올로기가 한층 돋보인 것은 예전과는 달리 일반대중이 전쟁과 평화의 문제를 직접 고려하는 역할을 수행함에 따라 이데올로기적 전망이 점차 중요하게 되었기 때문이다. 가령 1916년 연합국이 전쟁을 '민주주의를 위해 세계를 보호하는' 투쟁으로 생각하자고 촉구한 데 반해 독일은 야만에 대한 '문화' 투쟁으로 여기도록 부추겼다. 이같은 전쟁의도가 해당정부의 주요목표였는지는 별개의 문제이며, 중요한 것은 전쟁을 정당화할 필요성이 커짐에 따라 이 정당화가 이데올로기적 형태를 취했다는 점이다.

냉전 이데올로기

1950년대의 냉전은 대규모의 이데올로기적 대결로 이해해야 한다. 공산주의는 분명 이데올로기이지만, 서구의 비공산주의나 반공산주의도 소극적으로는 이데올로기이다. 그러나 하나의 이데올로기에 대한 반대가 반드시 다른 이데올로기에 속함을 의미하지는 않는다. 국제전쟁과 이데올로기의 연관성은 종류 차이보다는 오히려 정도 차이로 더 잘 나타낼 수 있다. 이데올로기적 전쟁과 비이데올로기적 전쟁 사이에 분명한 경계는 없으며 어떤 전쟁이 다른 전쟁보다 더 이데올로기적일 뿐이다. 과거의 종교전쟁을 떠올려보면 명백하다. 투르크에 대한 그리스도교 십자군 원정, 가톨릭과 프로테스탄트 사이의 종교적 갈등은 오늘날의 이데올로기적 갈등과 매우 큰 공통성을 갖는다. 그러나 과거의 이데올로기적 요소는 부차적이었던 반면 현대의 특징은 종교전쟁과 정치전쟁, 외교에서 이데올로기의 요소가 지배적인 것이 되었다는 점이다.

M. Cranston 글

 

Bibliography

BIBLIOGRAPHY. A useful introduction is M. SELIGER, Ideology and Politics (1976), which works from a broad definition of the concept of ideology. JOHN PLAMENATZ, Ideology (1970), is a clear and uncomplicated study by a distinguished Oxford philosopher. JEAN BAECHLER, Qu'est-ce que l'idéologie? (1976), is characteristically French in its approach and affords an equally lucid introduction to both the sociological and the historical aspects of the problem. Other books written at a fairly popular level include PATRICK CORBETT, Ideologies (1966); ROY C. MACRIDIS, Contemporary Political Ideologies: Movements and Regimes, 5th ed. (1992); and LEON P. BARADAT, Political Ideologies: Their Origins and Impact, 5th ed. (1993).

Few of the works of the original French idéologues are available in modern editions and even fewer in English translations. However, RICHARD H. COX (ed.), Ideology, Politics, and Political Theory (1969), contains short translated excerpts from Destutt de Tracy and his contemporaries as well as from more recent works. A.L.C. DESTUTT DE TRACY, A Treatise on Political Economy, trans. from French, rev. by THOMAS JEFFERSON (1817, reprinted 1973), is his major work in the field; and the expository study by FRANÇOIS JOSEPH PICAVET, Les Idéologues (1891, reprinted 1975), remains a classic. The life of Destutt de Tracy and his role in the origins of ideology are traced in EMMET KENNEDY, A Philosophe in the Age of Revolution: Destutt de Tracy and the Origins of "Ideology" (1978).

GEORGE LICHTHEIM, The Concept of Ideology (1967), contains a short but well-informed and sympathetic analysis of ideology as it figures in Hegelian and Marxist thought. LOUIS ALTHUSSER, Politics and History: Montesquieu, Rousseau, Hegel, and Marx, trans. from French (1972, reissued as both Politics and History: Montesquieu, Rousseau, and Marx and Montesquieu, Rousseau, Marx: Politics and History, 1982), traces the relationship between Hegelian and Marxist thought. G.W.F. HEGEL, Lectures on the Philosophy of History (1857, reissued 1956; originally published in German, 3rd ed., 1848), shows relevant elements in his philosophy. Valuable commentaries are provided by ALEXANDRE KOJÈVE, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel (1969, reissued 1980; originally published in French, 1947); CHARLES TAYLOR, Hegel (1975); and JEAN HYPPOLITE, Studies on Marx and Hegel (1969, reissued 1973; originally published in French, 1955). For Marxist philosophy, KARL MARX and FRIEDRICH ENGELS, The German Ideology, rev. ed., 2 vol. in 1 (1976; originally published in German, 1932), is the fundamental text. Recent treatments of ideology in the Marxist tradition include ALVIN W. GOULDNER, The Dialectic of Ideology and Technology (1976, reissued 1982); JORGE LARRAIN, The Concept of Ideology (1979, reprinted 1992), and Marxism and Ideology (1983, reprinted 1991); COLIN SUMNER, Reading Ideologies: An Investigation into the Marxist Theory of Ideology and Law (1979); and JOE McCARNEY, The Real World of Ideology (1980). More advanced students will find useful WALTER CARLSNAES, The Concept of Ideology and Political Analysis (1981).

Writers who have attempted to formulate a neo-Marxist theory of ideology, drawing in part on Hegelian philosophy, include HERBERT MARCUSE, One Dimensional Man (1964, reissued 1991); JÜRGEN HABERMAS, Toward a Rational Society (1971); and KARL MANNHEIM, Ideology and Utopia, new ed. (1991; originally published in German, 1929). Also worthy of attention are LOUIS ALTHUSSER, Essays on Ideology (1984); and RAYMOND BOUDON, The Analysis of Ideology (1989; originally published in French, 1986).

Interpretations of ideology that are directly opposed to Marxist theory include JAMES R. FLYNN, Humanism and Ideology (1973); LEWIS S. FEUER, Ideology and the Ideologists (1975); MARTIN SELIGER, The Marxist Conception of Ideology (1977); and D.J. MANNING (ed.), The Form of Ideology (1980). JEAN-PAUL SARTRE, Critique of Dialectical Reason (1976; originally published in French, 1960), constructs a theory of ideology as a "marginal system of ideas" that is consciously designed as an alternative to Marxist theory.

Historical studies that take a relatively extensive view of the impact of ideology as a revolutionary force in the modern world are JAMES H. BILLINGTON, Fire in the Minds of Men (1980); MELVIN J. LASKY, Utopia and Revolution (1976); and JEANNE HERSCH, Idéologies et réalité (1956). HANS KOHN, Political Ideologies of the Twentieth Century, 3rd ed. rev. (1966); ISAAC KRAMNICK and FREDERICK M. WATKINS, The Age of Ideology: Political Thought, 1750 to the Present, 2nd ed. (1979); and TRYGVE R. THOLFSEN, Ideology and Revolution in Modern Europe: An Essay on the Role of Ideas in History (1984), treat ideology as the dominant characteristic of modern political thinking. More polemical commentaries on the development of ideology include ALBERT CAMUS, The Rebel (1953, reissued 1991; originally published in French, 1951); JEAN FRANÇOIS REVEL, Pourquoi des philosophes? (1957, reissued 1976); and KARL POPPER, The Poverty of Historicism (1957, reissued 1986). A systematic critique of the whole notion of ideological politics may be found in MICHAEL OAKESHOTT, On Human Conduct (1975, reissued 1991), On History and Other Essays (1983), and Rationalism in Politics, new and expanded ed. (1991).

RAYMOND ARON, The Opium of the Intellectuals (1957, reprinted 1985; originally published in French, 1955), points to a decline in ideological politics in the West; as does DANIEL BELL, The End of Ideology, rev. ed. (1962, reissued 1988). Less confident views are advanced in DAVID E. APTER (ed.), Ideology and Discontent (1964); and SIDNEY HOOK, Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life (1975). An excellent compilation of the contrasting positions in the "End of Ideology" debate is CHAIM I. WAXMAN (ed.), The End of Ideology Debate (1968). FRANCIS FUKUYAMA, The End of History and the Last Man (1992), asserts that all ideological alternatives to liberal democracy have been discredited.

Sociological aspects of ideology are explored in DONALD G. MacRAE, Ideology and Society (1961); NORMAN BIRNBAUM, The Sociological Study of Ideology (1940-1960) (1962); ERIC CARLTON, Ideology and Social Order (1977); FRANÇOIS BOURRICAUD, Le Bricolage idéologique (1980); and GRAHAM C. KINLOCH, Ideology and Contemporary Sociological Theory (1981).

The relationship between ideology and political domination is examined in QUINTIN HOARE and GEOFFREY NOWELL SMITH (eds. and trans.), Selections from the Prison Notebooks of Antonio Gramsci (1971, reissued 1987). ARNE NAESS, Democracy, Ideology, and Objectivity (1956), written from the perspective of political philosophy, was the first of a series of works that investigate the relationship between ideology and liberty. Others worthy of mention are Z.A. JORDAN, Philosophy and Ideology (1963); JUDITH N. SHKLAR (ed.), Political Theory and Ideology (1966); DANTE GERMINO, Beyond Ideology (1967, reprinted 1976); and MAURICE CRANSTON and PETER MAIR (eds.), Ideology and Politics (1980). KENNETH MINOGUE, Alien Powers: The Pure Theory of Ideology (1985), uses both a philosophical and a historical approach to provide a far-reaching survey of the subject. Among books that stay close to the main tradition of American political science, the following are notable: ROBERT E. LANE, Political Ideology (1962); WILLIAM E. CONNOLLY, Political Science & Ideology (1967); and ROBERT A. DAHL, After the Revolution?, rev. ed. (1990). ANDREW GYORGY and GEORGE D. BLACKWOOD, Ideologies in World Affairs (1967), analyzes the emergence of ideology as a decisive factor in international relations. Students interested in such modern ideologies as environmentalism and animal rights should consult IAN ADAMS, Political Ideology Today (1993). (M.C./Ed.)

 

  • 참고문헌 (이데올로기)

    • 이데올로기란 무엇인가 : J. 플라메나츠, 진덕규 역, 까치, 1991
    • 이데올로기신론 : 한점수, 대왕사, 1991
    • 인식과 이데올로기 - 마르크스·레닌·만하임을 중심으로 : 칼스네스 월터, 박진환 역, 문우사, 1991
    • 정치학의 이데올로기 : H. 코온, 서울문학과 사회연구소 역, 청하, 1991
    • 현대사회와 이데올로기 : 유준수, 고려원, 1991
    • 현대정치이데올로기 : L. T. Sargent, 정세구 역, 교육과학사, 1991
    • 역사와 계급의식 : G. 루카치, 박정호 외 역, 거름, 1990
    • 이데올로기이론과 실천 : 배찬복, 법문사, 1990
    • 현대사회이론과 이데올로기 전2 : J. 라레인, 한상진 역, 한울, 1990-91
    • 이데올로기의 이해 : M. 크랜스턴, 이재석 역, 민족문화사, 1989
    • 정치경제학 비판을 위하여(중원문화신서 41) : K. 마르크스, 김호균 역, 중원문화, 1988
    • 이데올로기 : 김동익, 청람출판사, 1987
    • 이데올로기의 시대 : H. 에이킨, 이선일, 서광사, 1986
    • 일차원적 인간 : H. 마르쿠제, 박병진 역, 한마음사, 1986
    • 진리와 이데올로기 : 한스 바르트, 황경식 역, 종로서적, 1986
    • 이데올로기론 : 전득주, 박영사, 1985
    • 이데올로기의 종언 : D. , 이상두 역, 범우사, 1984
    • 이데올로기와 유토피아 : K. 만하임, 임석진 역, 지학사, 1983
    • 이데올로기 - 그 기원과 미래 : A. 굴드너, 김쾌상 역, 한벗, 1982
    • 이데올로기란 무엇인가 : 야곱 바리온 외, 김진욱 외 역, 종로서적, 1982
    • 도이치이데올로기 외 : K. 마르크스·F. 엥겔스 공저, 하기락 역, 형설출판사, 1982
    • 역사철학강의 Ⅰ·Ⅱ(세계사상전집 17·18) : G. W. F. 헤겔, 김종호 역, 삼성출판사, 1982
    • 이성적인 사회를 향하여 : J. 하버마스, 장일조 역, 종로서적, 1980
    • Alien PowerThe Pure Theory of Ideology : K. R. Minogue, 1985
    • The Form of Ideology : David Manning, 1980
    • Utopia and Revolution : Melvin J. Lasky, 1976
    • Ideology and Politics : Martin Seliger, 1976
    • The Concept of Ideology : George Lichtheim, 1967
    • Ideology and Society : Donald Macrae, 1961

 

   

[ 보수주의 ] [ 자유주의 ] [ 민족주의 ] [ 파시즘 ] [ 사회주의 ] [ 공산주의 ] [ 무정부주의 ]


[ ] [ 위로 ] [ 지식의 분야 ] [ 학파와 학설 ] [ 서양 철학사 ] [ 형이상학 ] [ 인식론 ] [ 윤리학 ] [ 미 학 ] [ 인류학 ] [ 이데올로기 ] [ 인문주의 ] [ 초월주의 ] [ 중국 철학 ] [ 인도 철학 ] [ 그리스 철학 ]


 
 
 

 게시판  검색  자료실  사이트맵  예수와나?

[ 뒤로 ] [ ] [ 위로 ] [ 다음 ]

 
 

Jesusi.com Homepage



This page was last modified 2001/06/11